A New History of Western Philosophy by Anthony Kenny

By Anthony Kenny

Less than is an outline switched over from the only Calibre scrapes for the book.

This ebook isn't any below a advisor to the entire of Western philosophy -- the tips that experience undergirded our civilization for two-and-a-half thousand years. Anthony Kenny tells the tale of philosophy from historical Greece during the center a long time and the Enlightenment into the fashionable international. He introduces us to the good thinkers and their rules, beginning with Plato, Aristotle, and the opposite founders of Western idea. within the moment a part of the e-book he's taking us via one thousand years
of medieval philosophy, and indicates us the wealthy highbrow legacy of Christian thinkers like Augustine, Aquinas, and Ockham. entering into the early smooth interval, we discover the good works of Descartes, Hobbes, Locke, Leibniz, Spinoza, Hume, and Kant, which stay crucial interpreting this day. within the
nineteenth and 20th centuries, Hegel, Mill, Nietzsche, Freud, and Wittgenstein back reworked the way in which we see the area.

Running even though the e-book are convinced issues which were consistent issues of philosophy in view that its early beginnings: the elemental questions of what exists and the way we will find out about it; the character of humanity, the brain, fact, and that means; where of God within the universe; how we must always dwell and the way society can be ordered. Anthony Kenny lines the advance of those issues throughout the centuries: we see how the questions requested and solutions provided through the nice philosophers of the previous
remain vividly alive this day.

Anyone drawn to rules and their background will locate this a desirable and stimulating read

Review

"Kenny's authoritative paintings, compiling 4 volumes, is the best single-author historical past of Western philosophy considering that Frederick Copleston- a Herculean job done with erudition and leisure. From the dream of the traditional Greeks to the deconstruction of postmodernists, he accessibly treats the most important branches of philosophy: ethics, politics, faith, epistemology, language, metaphysics, aesthetics, and common sense. --Christopher, Benson --First Things

About the Author

Sir Anthony Kenny is considered one of Britain's such a lot exclusive educational figures. He has been Pro-Vice-Chancellor of the college of Oxford, grasp of Balliol collage, Chairman of the Board of the British Library, and President of the British Academy. He has released greater than 40 books on philosophy and background.

Show description

Read or Download A New History of Western Philosophy PDF

Best philosophy books

Replacing Truth

Reviewed by means of David Ripley, college of Connecticut

In the 1st part or so of this publication, Kevin Scharp argues first that the idea that of fact (understood the following as one whose constitutive rules, taken jointly, have a few fake outcomes (p. 36)) is inconsistent; moment that it's thereby improper to be used in 'serious theorizing' (p. 134); and at last that it's going to get replaced with (consistent) successor recommendations designed so one can do the theoretical paintings we need fact to do. He devotes the rest of the booklet to the presentation, dialogue, and deployment of a specific pair of such successor techniques, which he dubs ascending fact and descending truth.

Chapter 1 quick surveys the significant philosophical literature on fact, dividing it into camps: 'philosophical approaches', which specialise in the character of fact itself, and 'logical approaches', which concentrate on constructing formal structures and tend to be paradox-focused. bankruptcy 2 provides a idea of inconsistent innovations. those are ideas with a few fake constitutive ideas; what it really is for a precept to be constitutive for an idea is naturally additionally thought of. (For Scharp, it's for possessors of the concept that to have default (and defeasible) entitlement to the main. )

Chapters three and four commence the flip to fact particularly, and make the case that fact is an inconsistent suggestion. bankruptcy three makes a speciality of what Scharp calls 'the seen argument' for truth's inconsistency: the argument to contradiction in keeping with the liar paradox. This calls for that fact obey the favourite T-schema T〈φ〉↔ φ for all sentences φ (in specific, for the liar sentence itself), the place T is the reality predicate and〈φ〉is a reputation of φ. Scharp divides the T-schema into its part ideas T〈φ〉→ φ (which I'll name 'release') and φ → T〈φ〉(which I'll name 'capture'), and argues, dependent partly on their an important function in truth's use as a tool of endorsement, that those rules are constitutive for the idea that fact. 'The seen argument' additionally is dependent upon the reasoning within the generic argument to contradiction being legitimate, and he argues for this declare besides (I will go back to this below). bankruptcy four bargains extra arguments for truth's inconsistency, all established round the phenomenon of revenge.

Chapter five begins from the concept fact is an inconsistent proposal, and argues that it's going to consequently get replaced, at the least for a few reasons. This comprises dialogue of, and arguments opposed to, different theories of fact that carry it to be inconsistent yet don't suggest changing it.

Chapter 6 starts the confident venture of the publication; in it Scharp develops what he calls the 'prescriptive theory' of fact. this is often the place the replacements that Scharp commends to us -- which he calls 'ascending truth' and 'descending truth' (on which extra lower than) -- are built and explored. bankruptcy 7 turns to reflections on technique. right here Scharp spells out what he calls 'metrological naturalism', a Davidson-inspired method of philosophical technique that is helping us see the best way to use specific innovations with out providing an research of them (in this situation, utilized to ascending fact and descending truth).

In bankruptcy eight Scharp considers the various theoretical makes use of fact serves for us, in theories of facts, objectivity, which means, reference, and so on. , and argues that ascending and descending fact can serve those reasons to boot. this is often an important to his total venture; if ascending and descending fact can't serve those reasons, then exchanging fact with them will be no higher than just throwing fact away and preventing there. during this bankruptcy, Scharp adapts a selected variety of truth-conditional semantics (which I'll abbreviate TCS) for traditional languages (based on Predelli 2005) to the current surroundings, changing it to ascending-truth-and-descending-truth-conditional semantics (which I'll abbreviate ATDTCS).

In bankruptcy nine Scharp turns to 'descriptive theory' -- how are we to appreciate what traditional audio system suggest once they declare that whatever is right? (And extra normally, how are we to appreciate usual makes use of of inconsistent thoughts? ) the following Scharp deploys the ATDTCS he develops within the past bankruptcy. Its deployment for this goal, even though, doesn't really depend upon the shift from TCS to ATDTCS; his idea of inconsistent techniques might simply in addition receive in a TCS formula (where it can volume to a specific type of assessment-sensitive theory). notwithstanding, Scharp has already argued that fact is improper for severe theorizing, and so is obliged to interchange TCS with ATDTCS.

Finally, bankruptcy 10 sums up, contemplating existence after 'the aletheic revolution' (that is, after fact is changed with the crew of ascending fact and descending truth), and responding to a few capability objections.

Evaluation

Replacing fact is wealthy and deeply lucrative, and that i won't have the ability to do it complete justice right here; as an alternative, i'm going to aspect to a couple of the explanations I'm occupied with it.

I suspect idea of inconsistent techniques (or anything within the quarter, anyways) is important for figuring out various philosophical (and different) puzzles. Scharp's cautious and persuasive paintings on inconsistent options (particularly in Chapters 2 and nine) repays learn and could be largely acceptable. This dialogue might be of curiosity to philosophers of language and ideas really typically, whether they are fascinated with fact or paradox. Scharp's method of inconsistent techniques doesn't itself require (although it truly is required by means of) the book's method of truth.

Scharp's transparent recognition to methodological matters is usually very welcome. In a couple of ordinary discussions (particularly logical discussions) of fact and paradoxes, it might probably occasionally be uncertain even if the unconventional formal structures offered are meant as thoughts for revisions in our perform with the reality predicate (Scharp's 'prescriptive theory' serves this purpose), or as ideas for revisions in our figuring out of our present perform (Scharp's 'descriptive theory' serves this purpose). Scharp by no means falls into this unclarity, and develops transparent, fascinating, and precise techniques of either varieties. This advances separate (but overlapping) debates, either via contributing to them and via making plainer simply how distinctive they are.

This is even sooner than we get to the book's major thrust: the arguments for changing fact, and the proposed replacements. those too are wealthy and worthwhile, and that i will interact in short with a number of facets of them under. yet quite, if this type of factor is in any respect your bag, learn the ebook; there's much in it worthy it slow. I'm simply going in an effort to comic strip a couple of fragments here.

The argument for replacement

Scharp's major argument (the 'obvious argument') that fact is an inconsistent inspiration is predicated at the liar paradox in a well-recognized method: due to the fact there's a legitimate argument to contradiction from truth's constitutive rules, fact has to be an inconsistent proposal. to ensure that the most obvious argument to paintings, it can be crucial that proposed resolutions of the liar paradox don't achieve resolving it. fact needs to be surely inconsistent for Scharp's method of paintings. when you consider that virtually not anyone thinks that a couple of proposed solution is workable (and many people doubt it's even that many! ), each one of Scharp's conclusions right here (this process doesn't paintings, that method doesn't paintings, and so on. ) can be congenial to so much readers.

Nonetheless, i would like to target one element of the general argument, and recommend that whatever is amiss. the difficulty arises in Scharp's attention of methods to fact in accordance with nonclassical logics. As he issues out (p. 81), no nontrivial logical procedure (with a wealthy adequate conception of syntax) can settle for all of one) modus ponens and conditional facts (for an analogous conditional connective), 2) 'the usual structural ideas for derivability' (in specific transitivity and contraction), and three) catch and release.

Scharp additionally argues right here that modus ponens and conditional facts are constitutive ideas of the conditional, and that transitivity and contraction are constitutive of 'the derivability operator' (p. 81). He had past argued that the trap and liberate are constitutive of fact. therefore, the constitutive rules of these types of issues taken jointly yield triviality, in order that they can't all be right. Assuming the conclusions of Scharp's part arguments, both the conditional, or validity, or fact should have a few flawed constitutive ideas, and so be an inconsistent notion. yet why is he so certain it's truth?

The resolution turns out to have anything to do with attaining the precise point of generality, specifically ensuring to not overgeneralize. Scharp offers:

the case for adopting a non-classical good judgment . . . . shouldn't be made by means of attempting to accommodate the constitutive ideas of a few different idea that is classically inconsistent. i feel this aspect could be made opposed to any try and regulate our common sense within the face of paradoxes. convinced, lets accomplish that, yet this stream is a "language-wide" swap, this means that arguments having not anything to do with the idea that in query (truth in our case) that have been formerly thought of legitimate, will develop into invalid. (p. 81)

For instance, to say that modus ponens is the faulty constitutive precept might have an effect on our theories of validity around the board, even if no paradoxes are involved.

I absolutely advocate the will to not overgeneralize, to maintain our ways to paradox from ramifying too generally and 'fixing' what wasn't damaged. I fear, although, that Scharp's truth-focused process has the other challenge: it undergeneralizes, lacking universal beneficial properties among paradoxes that do and paradoxes that don't contain truth.

Let's wear our inspector hats and escape the magnifying glasses. There's a wave of paradoxes sweeping town, and we have to locate the wrongdoer sooner than they strike back. There are liar paradoxes and curry paradoxes, restricted-quantification curries (Beall et al. , 2006) and validity curries (Shapiro, 2011; Beall and Murzi, 2013), russells and Hinnion-Liberts (Hinnion and Libert, 2003; Restall, 2013), all with a standard modus operandi. [1]

To slim down our checklist of suspects, it is smart to invite: Who was once at each of the crime scenes? utilizing this technique, logical vocabulary all comes out within the transparent. It's no longer negation; he was once out of city whilst the curries occurred. It's no longer the conditional; she used to be nowhere close to the liars (assuming, besides, that negation isn't simply the conditional with a fake moustache on). yet fact comes out within the transparent too: it's bought an outstanding alibi for the russells, the Hinnion-Liberts, and the validity curries (as good as knowers and Montagues). in truth, there are just characters that happen in any respect of the crime scenes: contraction and transitivity, either issues Scharp claims are constitutive for validity. we should always be very convinced certainly that validity isn't our offender sooner than we spend an excessive amount of time harassing truth.

Since contraction and transitivity either practice to our whole language, the concern of overgeneralization obviously returns; with out the sort of, won't our reasoning be crippled around the board, even if paradoxes don't threaten in any respect? yet no less than when it comes to transitivity, this is often demonstrably no longer so: there are nontransitive logics that validate all classically-valid arguments including a completely naive conception of fact, whereas ultimate nontrivial (see, e. g. , Ripley, 2013). Given Scharp's different perspectives, then, I reckon he should still take heavily the concept it's validity, instead of fact, that's an inconsistent notion -- certainly the inconsistent idea on the middle of the paradoxes. (Scharp in brief considers the concept validity is inconsistent (p. 218), yet for various purposes, and with no pursuing it. )

The proffered replacements

Having argued that fact could be changed, Scharp proposes to exchange it with a couple of options: ascending fact and descending fact. The names are might be deceptive; neither of those recommendations is a type of fact in any respect -- that's the entire element! that's, regardless of the names, being ascending real and being descending real usually are not methods of being actual; they're different statuses solely. (Scharp occasionally speaks of 'ascending and descending truth', but when we're being cautious this could strike us just like 'The League of and The United Nations'. )

Scharp provides an axiomatisation, which he calls ADT, of ascending and descending fact. (ADT isn't intended to be the complete tale approximately ascending and descending fact, yet really a tremendous sub-story (p. 153). ) in line with ADT, the declare that φ is descending actual, which I'll write D〈φ〉, is not less than as robust as φ itself, yet in all probability more advantageous. The declare that φ is ascending real, which I'll write A〈φ〉, is no less than as vulnerable as φ itself, yet very likely weaker. that's, D〈φ → φ and φ → A〈φ〉 are theorems of ADT, yet their converses aren't. additionally, ascending and descending fact are duals; a sentence is descending precise iff its negation isn't ascending real, and ascending precise iff its negation isn't really descending actual. (This is simply a small a part of ADT; I won't current the axiomatisation in complete the following, yet will as a substitute concentration simply on a few of its extra notable good points. )

It is feasible to work out during this a 'splitting' of the widespread T-schema, T〈φ〉↔ φ. Descending fact takes over the left-to-right course of this equivalence, and ascending fact takes over the right-to-left path. (Ascending fact 'captures' yet doesn't 'release'; descending fact 'releases' yet doesn't 'capture'. ) it may be tempting to imagine (and it truly is occasionally precise) that different primary alethic rules will paintings like this besides, yet this isn't regularly so; a few care is needed. for instance, we frequently anticipate a fact predicate to validate the followingconjunction schema: (T φ ∧ T〈ψ〉) ↔ T〈φ ∧ ψ〉. The instructions of this schema, even though, will not be break up among ascending and descending fact; neither of them validates the left-to-right course of the conjunction schema, whereas either validate the right-to-left path as a substitute. (The left-to-right course is secured on a combined analyzing: (D〈φ〉∧ D〈ψ) → A〈φ ∧ ψ〉is a theorem (p. 171). )

As the instance of the conjunction schema exhibits, neither ascending nor descending fact is closed below multi-premise validity (since φ, ψ ⊢ φ ∧ ψ); neither is both of them closed less than single-premise validity. nor is even closed less than alternative of logical equivalents (p. 173). that's, there are sentences φ and ψ such that φ ↔ ψ is a theorem, and D〈φ〉is a theorem, yet D〈ψ〉is no longer. (In truth, there are instances like this the place ¬D〈ψ〉is a theorem. for instance, allow φ be an axiom of ADT, and allow ψ be the 'descending liar' mentioned lower than. ) this may take a few being used to.

A sentence φ is 'safe' iff A〈φ〉→ D〈φ〉; for secure sentences, ascending fact and descending fact are similar (since D〈φ〉→ A〈φ〉 is a theorem of ADT for each φ), and because φ is usually sandwiched among D〈φ〉and A〈φ〉, it too is such as those while it really is secure. For secure sentences, then, we will be able to ignore the excellence among ascending and descending fact, and deal with them (more or much less) as we'd deal with fact, have been it current. (For instance, the place φ ∧ ψ is secure, descending fact will fulfill the total conjunction schema above; the place either φ and ψ are secure, ascending fact will. ) yet for detrimental sentences φ, there are 3 separate claims to maintain song of: D〈φ〉, A〈φ〉, and φ itself.

Scharp proves that ADT is constant (relative to ZFC) model-theoretically, through constructing buildings he calls 'xeno models'. those are a piece kludgey: they mix local types for modal good judgment with extra formula-indexed accessibility kin with revision sequences on best. yet regardless of the kitchen-sink nature of Scharp's consistency evidence, it's quite straight forward to get a believe for the way ADT remains constant: it's a mix of a classical glut concept and a classical hole idea (see box, 2008 for discussion).

To see what I suggest, reflect on the 'descending liar': a sentence δ that's ¬D〈δ〉. If δ is descending real, then it's not descending actual (since D〈φ〉→ φ for any φ, and because δ says that it isn't descending true); so it isn't descending real. we have now proved δ itself. yet this can be the place it stops; there's no solution to get to any hassle from the following, on account that there's no technique to finish from δ itself that δ is descending true.

Taking inventory, δ is ascending real yet no longer descending actual; it's dangerous. like any detrimental sentences, its negation is usually damaging. (If ¬φ is secure, then ¬φ is both descending precise or it isn't ascending actual. If ¬φ is descending real, then φ can't be ascending precise, because A and D are twin, and so φ is secure. If ¬φ isn't really ascending real, then φ is descending real, because A and D are twin, and so φ is secure. ) that's, each harmful sentence is such that either it and its negation are ascending precise, and neither it nor its negation is descending actual. ADT, whereas absolutely classical, is a idea of ascending gluts and descending gaps; the damaging sentences fall into those categories.

Like all classical glut and classical hole theories, then, it has a few sticky issues round the paradoxes. it's not like δ and its negation have an analogous prestige in ADT; in the end, δ is a theorem of ADT (and its negation, as a result, can't be extra to ADT on discomfort of contradiction). yet this distinction in prestige can't be mentioned in ADT itself; either δ and its negation are ascending precise, nor is descending actual, and people are the one correct statuses that may be mentioned. What, then, is the variation among them? it sort of feels transparent: in keeping with ADT, δ is correct, yet its negation isn't. yet ADT has been designed to not have the capacity to exhibit this.

Note, during this connection, that Scharp's proposed ATDTCS can't get at this contrast both: δ and its negation (or their usual language equivalents) have exactly the related ascending and descending fact stipulations as one another. (They are either regularly ascending precise, and not descending precise. ) but they need to range in that means, on account that one is correct, and the opposite isn't. It doesn't require 'true' to specific the purpose. the next schema might be very traditional for a consistentist like Scharp: 'if φ and ¬ψ, then 〈φ〉 and 〈ψ〉 range in meaning'. yet this precept is incompatible with ATDTCS, given ADT.

We also needs to count on ADT, as a classical gap/glut thought, to stand problems approximately truth's position as a tool of endorsement; and this expectation is born out. Scharp makes a couple of claims in changing fact. between them is the declare that δ isn't really descending actual (p. 173); that's, between them is δ itself. think i need to propose the contents of Scharp's booklet with no repeating the whole thing myself. How am i able to do it, after the aletheic revolution? i will not say 'Everything during this ebook is descending true'; this is often to disagree with the contents of the ebook, as a result of the harmful sentences asserted in it (together with the claims that they're unsafe). yet descending fact is Scharp's proposed alternative for fact in its function as a tool of endorsement (p. 174).

Ascending fact won't paintings as a tool of endorsement both -- announcing that anything is ascending precise is simply too vulnerable to count number as endorsing it -- and Scharp doesn't provide it as one. He does suggest ascending fact to be used in rejection, yet duality guarantees it has an identical challenge in rejections as descending fact does in endorsements.

In areas, Scharp recognizes those difficulties yet minimizes them ('there isn't any such factor as a constant real gadget of endorsement. Descending fact is as shut as it is easy to [consistently] get' (p. 281)). somewhere else, he leaves them offstage fullyyt ('ascending and descending fact, jointly, can practice truth's expressive function. that's, they could function units of endorsement and rejection' (p. 156, the place hazardous sentences are a great deal dialectically relevant)).

It is critical, even though, to maintain those obstacles in brain, relatively simply because they aren't not obligatory. it isn't as if, had Scharp in basic terms been extra shrewdpermanent, he can have designed constant replacements that meet his different desiderata and nonetheless totally serve truth's expressive position; no such replacements are attainable. there's simply no approach, the way in which Scharp proceeds, to take away the inconsistency from fact with no while elimination a few of its usefulness. exchanging fact, like changing fact, is and has to be fraught with compromise.

Despite this, i locate the publication very effective to have interaction with; its imaginative and prescient, readability of objective, and creativity all are available in huge measures. even though I'm lovely definite exchanging Truth's method of the paradoxes is barking up the incorrect tree, I'm additionally convinced I'll be returning to the booklet for a while; Scharp's voice is imperative during this conversation.

REFERENCES

Beall, J. , Brady, R. T. , Hazen, A. P. , Priest, G. , and Restall, G. (2006). appropriate limited quantification. magazine of Philosophical good judgment, 35(6): 587-598.

Beall, J. and Murzi, J. (2013). flavors of Curry's paradox. magazine of Philosophy, 110(3):143-165.

Field, H. (2008). Saving fact from Paradox. Oxford college Press, Oxford.

Hinnion, R. and Libert, T. (2003). optimistic abstraction and extensionality. magazine of Symbolic good judgment, 68(3): 828-836.

Predelli, S. (2005). Contexts: that means, fact, and using Language. Oxford college Press, Oxford.

Priest, G. (2002). past the bounds of inspiration. Oxford collage Press, Oxford.

Restall, G. (2013). statement, denial, and non-classical theories. In Tanaka, ok. , Berto, F. , Mares, E. , and Paoli, F. , editors, Paraconsistency: common sense and purposes, pp. 81-100. Springer, Dordrecht.

Ripley, D. (2013). Paradoxes and screw ups of lower. Australasian magazine of Philosophy, 91(1): 139-164.

Shapiro, L. (2011). Deflating logical final result. Philosophical Quarterly, 61(243): 320-342.

This 'common' is naturally contentious. particularly, Graham Priest's 'inclosure schema' (Priest, 2002) attracts a shiny line among liars and their kinfolk on one facet and curries and their kin at the different. i'd make a similar objection, then, to the inclosure schema.

[1] This 'common' is naturally contentious. particularly, Graham Priest's 'inclosure schema' (Priest, 2002) attracts a shiny line among liars and their family on one aspect and curries and their family at the different. i might make an analogous objection, then, to the inclosure schema.

Contarini, and the Religious Republic of Letters

Although the paradigm of modernist development has been challenged on many fronts, Erasmus and different sixteenth-century figures are nonetheless regularly seen as those who led the transition from a spiritual heart a long time to a extra godless smooth period. by means of examining the lives, paintings, and correspondence of Erasmus, Thomas extra, Margaret extra Roper, Reginald Pole, Gasparo Contarini, and Vittoria Colonna, this ebook demonstrates how those Catholic women and men of letters created a particular type of spiritual neighborhood rooted in friendship and spiritualized scholarship.

The Ontology of Socratic Questioning in Plato's Early Dialogues (SUNY Series in Ancient Greek Philosophy)

A provocative shut studying revealing a thorough, proto-phenomenological Socrates.

Modern interpreters of Plato’s Socrates have ordinarily taken the dialogues to be geared toward figuring out target fact. Attending heavily to the texts of the early dialogues and the query of advantage specifically, Sean D. Kirkland means that this procedure is flawed—that such drawback with getting to know exterior proof rests on smooth assumptions that may were faraway from the minds of Socrates and his contemporaries. This isn’t, besides the fact that, to accuse Socrates of any type of relativism. via cautious research of the unique Greek and of more than a few competing strands of Plato scholarship, Kirkland as a substitute brings to gentle an intensive, proto-phenomenological Socrates, for whom “what advantage is” is what has regularly already seemed as virtuous in daily event of the realm, whether preliminary appearances are unsatisfactory or imprecise and wanting higher scrutiny and rationalization.

Additional resources for A New History of Western Philosophy

Example text

The penises of all those men, their verges, tingling? Undoubtedly. Yet something else in the air too. Worship. 23 —Translated by John McKeane, with Jeff Fort Preamble ................. 18180$ $CH1 12-22-11 14:58:07 PS 21 PAGE 21 Re-opening the Question of Religion Dis-enclosure of Religion and Modernity in the Philosophy of Jean-Luc Nancy A L E N A A L E X A N D R O VA , I G N A A S D E V I S C H , L A U R E N S T E N K AT E , A N D A U K J E VA N R O O D E N A Return to Religion? ’’ What at first sight appears to be a simple return to religious values, inspired by a critical rejection of the basic assumptions of modern secular culture, is in fact a refined dialogue with this culture, a dialogue in which religious and secular arguments often change places.

There is no historical development or even progress: from presecular to secular and on to a postsecular era. Nevertheless, the term post-secular, has become important for all we have attempted to think the ‘‘return of/to religion’’ in the last decade. The proclamation of a post-secular society by an increasing number of scholars, artists, and politicians is informed either by a criticism or even a rejection of secularism in favor of a certain rehabilitation of religion— from traditional monotheistic religion to new, individually created forms of spirituality—or by the recognition that a secular world cannot simply be atheistic, so that ‘‘something,’’ whether the religious or the nonsecular, must be given a place within it in order to render it viable in our time.

A vein that dissipates observance in adoration. More than one mystic from each tradition confirms this for us. However, the Jewish and the Muslim religions remain religions, very rich and complex systems of representation and observance, and it is difficult to see how they could be ‘‘secularized’’ (whatever the precise concept of the word might be). This is because they have no reason to enter into tension or conflict with institutions comparable to those of Christian Churches. The absence of such ‘‘Churches’’ obviously plays an important role here, one that has often been commented upon.

Download PDF sample

Rated 4.82 of 5 – based on 4 votes